Here begins the serialization of the long version of my paper, "Color-Consciousness Conceptualism," the short version of which appeared in the Second Annual Conference of
Consciousness Online.
AbstractI defend against a certain line of attack the view that the conscious contents of color experiences are exhausted by, or at least matched by, the concepts brought to bear in experience by the perceiver. The line of attack is an allegedly empirical argument against conceptualism—the Diachronic Indistinguishability Argument (DIA)—based on color pairs the members of which are too similar to be distinguished across a memory delay but are sufficiently distinct to be distinguished in simultaneous presentations. I sketch a model of a conceptualist view of conscious color perception that is immune to DIA. One distinctive feature of the conceptualism on offer here is that it does not rely upon the widely discussed and widely criticized demonstrative-concepts strategy popularized by John McDowell and others. I offer both empirical and philosophical considerations in my criticisms of the DIA and my sketch of my non-demonstrative conceptualism.
0. IntroductionIs there a mismatch between what we experience and what we conceptualize that might be best described in terms of fineness of grain? Are our experiences of color, in particular, more fine-grained than we are able to grasp in conceptualized thought? The goal of the present paper is to defend against a certain line of attack the view that conscious experience of color is no more fine-grained that the repertoire of non-demonstrative concepts that a perceiver is able to bring to bear in perception. The line of attack in question is an alleged empirical argument—the Diachronic Indistinguishability Argument (DIA)—based on pairs of colors sufficiently distinct to be discriminated when presented side-by-side but too similar to be discriminated across a memory delay. The DIA was developed by Raffman (1995) and it or arguments similar have been endorsed by Kelly (2001a) and Prinz (2007, pp. 192-193).[1] [2]My aim here is to show that this argument fails. My aim is not to give arguments in favor of the kind of conceptualism I favor. I do that elsewhere (Mandik, 2008, forthcoming).
The organization of the remainder is as follows: In sections 1-3 I spell out further preliminaries and relevant historical background. In section 4 I spell out the Diachronic Indistinguishability Argument and in section 5 I spell out my main criticism of it. Sections 6-9 are dedicated to objections and replies.
1. Demonstrative and non-demonstrative conceptualismsAt the center of many core debates concerning whether perceptual experience has nonconceptual content have been conceptualists who lean on a notion of demonstrative concepts to fend off worries about experiential fineness of grain. Especially prominent examples include McDowell (1994, 1998) and Brewer (1999, 2005). I will call such conceptualism “demonstrative conceptualism” for its reliance on demonstratives.
I will contrast demonstrative conceptualism with a view I will call “non-demonstrative conceptualism.” Note, however, I do not take the difference between demonstrative and non-demonstrative conceptualism to be a disagreement over whether there are such concepts as demonstrative concepts. The non-demonstrative conceptualist can remain neutral on that question. The key contrast, as I intend it, is over whether considerations having to do with fineness of grain are best dealt with by appeal to demonstrative concepts. In the present paper I will be defending a version of non-demonstrative conceptualism.
There are several motivations for conceptualism. And though the following is not intended to be exhaustive, it will nonetheless be useful to note a few of them. I will sort the motivating considerations into those that are primarily epistemological and those that are primarily metaphysical.
Epistemological motivations for conceptualism. One epistemological consideration motivating many conceptualists, and perhaps the motivation most discussed in the debates over whether perceptual experience has nonconceptual content, is the idea that perceptual experience serves to justify empirical beliefs, and can only play this justificatory role if it itself is, like the empirical beliefs is justifies, a conceptual state (Bengson, Grube, & Korman, in press; Brewer, 1999, 2005; McDowell, 1994). Another epistemological consideration that has motivated some philosophers is the thought that we have an especially high degree certainty about our own conscious states that is best accounted for by denying that our conscious states have an existence separable from our conceptualizations (thoughts, judgments, etc.) of them (Horgan & Kriegel, 2007, pp. 135-138; Lynch, 2006; Mandik, 2008, forthcoming; Rey, 1991, p. 100, 1993, p. 250).
Metaphysical motivations for conceptualism. Many theories of consciousness are argued for on the premises that a conscious state’s being conscious consists in one’s being conscious of the state, and that this consciousness of the state is implemented by one’s having a representation of the state (Carruthers, 2004; Kriegel, 2003, 2006; Lycan, 1996; Rosenthal, 2005; Van Gulick, 2004). On some versions, especially the higher-order thought theory of consciousness as defended by David Rosenthal, in order, for example, to be conscious of one’s perception as being of some color shade, one must have a suitable higher-order thought of that shade, which in turn requires that one have the conceptual resources needed to capture that color (2005, pp. 188-189). A distinct metaphysical motivation for holding conceptualism is less focal than that of the higher-order thought theorists. Instead of relying on a specific claim on the requirements on conscious states, this distinct motivation makes a general claim about mental states by way of a certain kind of appeal to parsimony: by seeking to explain all mental states as conceptual, we achieve a satisfying parsimony in our theorizing about the mind (Rey, 1991, p. 93, 1993, p. 248).[3]
The motives so far discussed are general motivations for adopting conceptualism. These general motivations do not alone suffice to motivate the particular version I am calling demonstrative conceptualism. The motive for demonstrative conceptualism arises in response to worries having to do with the fineness of grain of the conscious experience of color. The basic idea here is that without a recourse to demonstrative concepts, there just are not enough concepts possessed by a person to account for all of the colors that the person is nonetheless able to consciously perceive. To illustrate: a person may be able to perceive, perhaps on two separate occasions, two shades of red that differ in some slight way. If the person conceives of each of them simply as red, then it looks like there are differences in the perceived shades that outstrip the way they are conceived, since they are conceived in the same way. But by allowing, in addition to the concept RED, demonstrative concepts such as THIS SHADE and THAT SHADE, the demonstrative conceptualist prima facie provides for as many conceptualizations of colors as colors consciously perceived.
There have been various criticisms waged against demonstrative conceptualism (Dokic & Pacherie, 2001; Eilan, 2001; Kelly, 2001a, 2001b; Peacocke, 1998, 2001; Prinz, 2007). For present purposes, it will do to just focus on two general lines of complaint against demonstrative conceptualism.
The first line of complaint stems from what we might call the object-involving or externalistic individuation conditions on demonstrative contents. Such conditions are plausible and independently motivated. But this is not the problem. The problem is that also plausible and independently motivated are certain conditions on the phenomenal character of perceptual experience, conditions that seem not to appropriately “line up” with the aforementioned conditions on demonstrative contents. The conditions on phenomenal character may be briefly conveyed here as being closely connected with, if not identical to, the way things perceptually appear to the perceiving subject. The failure of “line-up” between demonstrative contents comes in two varieties. The first involves situations in which there can be a difference of perceptual appearance but sameness of demonstrative content, as when one and the same shade of a painted surface is demonstrated across different times while a dissipating fog intervening between perceiver and the perceived surface gives rise to differences in the appearance of the shade (Kelly, 2001a, p. 398 footnote 392). The second involves situations in which there can be a sameness of perceptual appearance but difference in demonstrative content, as when, on two different occasions two distinct entities are demonstrated, but the properties that serve to distinguish the entities do not suffice to make the entities discriminable in appearance (Davies, 1992, pp. 25-26).[4]
The second line of complaint against demonstrative conceptualism, and perhaps the one most prominent in recent discussions, concerns the worry that so-called demonstrative concepts seem not to be genuine concepts for they seem not to satisfy an alleged constraint on concept possession that we can, following (Chuard, 2006) call the Re-identification constraint. That there is some such criterion on concept possession is endorsed by several philosophers and criticized by Chuard (2006).[5] The gist of the Re-identification constraint can be stated as follows: In order to possess some concept, C, a possessor must be capable of, on multiple occasions, identifying as such entities properly conceptualized under that concept. So, for example, a person in genuine possession of the concept DOG must be capable, on multiple occasions, of conceiving of an entity as a dog. It seems, however, that there are situations in which we can demonstrate a color shade yet not be able to reidentify that shade. I might demonstrate some shade of a paint chip at a paint store (I say “let’s paint our apartment this color” while holding up the chip), and then accidentally drop it into a pile of very similarly colored chips. After dropping it, I may be at a total loss to say whether it is the chip I had previously demonstrated. If reidentifiability is a genuine constraint on concept possession, then whatever conditions sufficed for me to demonstrate the initial shade were insufficient conditions for me to grasp a concept of that shade as such.
Whereas demonstrative conceptualism leans on demonstrative resources to respond to worries about experiential fineness of grain, nondemonstrative conceptualism leans on other resources. One might view both demonstrative and nondemonstrative conceptualism as motivated by a worry about whether there is a general kind of conceptualist resource that can be marshaled to defuse worries that there is an upper bound on the number conceptualizations accessible to a perceiver. What general kind of resource is there besides demonstratives that would allow conceptualists to go beyond what might otherwise seem to be an upper bound? A natural suggestion is to borrow a strategy from elsewhere in the philosophy of mind for dealing with looming upper-bounds: appeal to the indefinite number of combinations achievable with a finite-stock of recombinable elements (Fodor, 1975, 2008).
To my knowledge, such a nondemonstrative conceptualism has not been spelled out at length, though there have been some brief discussions of it. Chuard (2006) brings it up briefly in a footnote but dismisses it quickly.[6] Rosenthal (2005, pp. 188-189) can be read as having a favorable view of such a strategy (a view that Gennaro (forthcoming) endorses), but his treatment of it is brief.
The gist of this combinatoric, non-demonstrative strategy may be spelled out in the manner of Rosenthal’s treatment. The conceptualist may appeal to combinations of two kinds of color concepts, what Rosenthal calls comparative and noncomparative color concepts. Comparative color concepts are those brought to bear in comparisons between colors, concepts such as the concept of one shade’s being darker than another or more blue than another. Noncomparative color concepts are those, such as red and vermillion, that are applicable in judgments that aren’t comparisons of colors. The gist of this version of conceptualism is that it is the view that for any color a perceiver can consciously experience something as, the perceiver must bring to bear in experience some color concept or combination of color concepts. So, for example, I may, on some conscious perceptual encounter with a shade, conceptualize it as vermillion (a noncomparative color concept). Alternately, I might, if lacking the concept vermillion, conceptualize it as more red than orange, and/or more orange than blood-red. Alternately, on a presentation of two shades of red side-by-side, I might conceive of the one on the right as a darker shade of red than the one on the left.
NOTES:
[1] As I interpret the DIA, and as it seems, Raffman intends it, it is an empirical argument. I have doubts about whether Kelly (2001) endorses the empirical argument. He seems, at least in places, to instead have an a priori argument in mind. See, especially his remark, “It's perfectly conceivable, in other words, and there's nothing about the nature of perception to keep it from being true, that our capacity to discriminate colors exceeds our capacity to re-identify the colors discriminated.” (p. 411, emphasis added).
[2] For discussion of the empirical evidence that, in various sensory modalities, our abilities of perceptual discrimination are more fine-grained than our memory and categorization abilities, see (Burns & Ward, 1977; Halsey & Chapanis, 1951; Hardin, 1988a; Hurvich, 1981).
[3] Rey (1993) writes:
[B]y assimilating [qualitative] experience to [propositional] attitudes, we explain the essential unity of the mind, what it is that makes beliefs, desires, memories, hopes, fears and sensations all states of the same sort of entity. What are sometimes proposed as rival accounts seem to me to lack this unity. For example, biologistic or dualistic accounts that regard qualia as biological or as entirely non-physical properties of a computationally organized brain have trouble explaining how a mind that thinks by computing manages to feel by being in some further non-computational relation to such further properties. The further properties seem gratuitous and accidental: unless they were somehow represented in that life, how could they be any more a part of a person’s mental life than the colour of their brain? But then why should not the representations be enough, whether or not there are the corresponding properties? (p. 248)
It should be noted that there is a bit of a wrinkle involved in counting Rey as a conceptualist. In his (Rey, 2007) he writes that on his view, sensational representations are ‘non-conceptual’ (scare-quotes, Rey’s) for not freely combining with each other (p. 115). Further, on Rey’s view, there are no qualia, just the contents of phenomenal concepts (p. 130). On one reading then, Rey is a conceptualist for denying that qualia have any existence beyond the contents of certain concepts. On a different reading though, Rey is a nonconceptualist for his view that sensational representations aren’t concepts.
[4] The demonstrative conceptualist may attempt to avoid these sorts of problems by, as Kelly (2001a, p. 398, note 2) suggests, having the demonstrative content be fixed, not by the shade that is experienced, but instead by the shade as it is experienced. However, such a move seems to make the resultant demonstrative conceptualism highly vulnerable to what Bermúdez & Cahen (2010) call the priority argument, the gist of which that is pertinent here is that experiential content is supposed to be explained by appeal to conceptual content, not the other way around (see also Heck (2000)). However, the appeal to, instead of the shade of color the external object actually has, the shade of color as it appears to experience, seems to invert the proper order of explanation.
[5] Examples of supporters of the Re-identification constraint include Brewer (1999), Jacob & Jeannerod (2003), Kelly (2001a, 2001b), McDowell (1994), and Prinz (2007).
[6] In Chuard (2006, p. 196, note 11) he writes:
Perhaps, one could reach the same result without resorting to demonstrative concepts. Suppose that a subject S possesses some chromatic concepts like RED and GREEN, together with concepts of ILLUMINATION, HUE, SATURATION, etc. She may then be able to form enough complex concepts composed out of those simpler concepts, so as to conceptualize the fine-grained differences between the shades she perceptually discriminates. The problem with this suggestion is that a subject might in fact lack even some basic chromatic concepts, not to mention concepts of ILLUMINATION, HUE and SATURATION.
Chuard here dismisses the nondemonstrative strategy on the grounds of a modal claim concerning what a subject might experience while lacking certain concepts. I find the modal claim to here be inadequately defended. As it appears in Chuard’s note, it is a bald assertion.
REFERENCES:
Bengson, J., Grube, E., & Korman, D. (in press). A New Framework for Conceptualism. Nous.
Berlin, B., & Kay, P. (1969). Basic color terms. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.
Bermúdez, J., & Cahen, A. (2010). Nonconceptual Mental Content. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brewer, B. (2005). Do Sense Experiential States Have Conceptual Content? In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (pp. 217-230). Oxford: Blackwell.
Burns, E. M., & Ward, W. D. (1977). Categorical perception — phenomenon or epiphenomenon: Evidence from experiments in the perception of musical intervals. . Journal of the Acoustical Society of America(63), 456-468.
Carruthers, P. (2004). HOP over FOR, HOT theory. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: an anthology (pp. 115-135). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
Chuard, P. (2006). Demonstrative concepts without re-identification. Philosophical Studies, 130(2), 153-201.
Craik, F. I. M., & Lockhart, R. S. (1972). Levels of processing: A framework for memory research1. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 11(6), 671-684.
Davies, M. (1992). Perceptual Content and Local Supervenience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 92, 21-45.
Deutsch, M. (2005). Intentionalism and Intransitivity. Synthese, 144(1), 1-22.
Dokic, J., & Pacherie, E. (2001). Shades and Concepts. Analysis 61(3), 193–202.
Eilan, N. (2001). Consciousness, Acquaintance and Demonstrative Thought. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(2), 433–440.
Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. (2008). LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goodman, N. (1951). The structure of appearance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Grush, R. (2007). A plug for generic phenomenology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5-6), 504-505.
Halsey, R. M., & Chapanis, A. (1951). Number of absolute identifiable hues. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 41, 1057-1058.
Hardin, C. L. (1988a). Color for Philosophers: Hackett.
Hardin, C. L. (1988b). Phenomenal colors and sorites. Nous, 22, 213-234.
Heck Jr, R. G. (2000). Nonconceptual Content and the "Space of Reasons". Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483-523.
Hellie, B. (2005). Noise and perceptual indiscriminability. Mind, 114(455), 481-508.
Horgan, T., & Kriegel, U. (2007). Phenomenal epistemology: What is consciousness that we may know it so well? Philosophical Issues, 17(1), 123-144.
Hurvich, L. M. (1981). Color vision. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.
Jacob, P., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of Seeing: the Scope and Limits of Visual Cognition Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Judd, D. B., & Wyszecki, G. (1963). Color in Business, Science and Industry (2 ed.). New York and London: John Wiley and Sons.
Kelly, S. D. (2001a). Demonstrative Concepts and Experience. The Philosophical Review, 110, 397-420.
Kelly, S. D. (2001b). The Non-conceptual Content of Perceptual Experience: Situation Dependence and Fineness of Grain. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62(3), 601–608.
Kriegel, U. (2003). Consciousness as Intransitive Self-Consciousness: Two Views and an Argument. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33, 103-132.
Kriegel, U. (2006). The Same-Order Monitoring Theory of Consciousness. In U. Kriegel & K. Williford (Eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness (pp. 143-170). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lotto, R., & Purves, D. (2002). The empirical basis of color perception. Consciousness and Cognition 11, 609-629.
Lycan, W. (1996). Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lynch, M. (2006). Zombies and the Case of the Phenomenal Pickpocket. Synthese, 149, 37-58.
Mandik, P. (2006). The Introspectibility of Brain States as Such. In B. Keeley (Ed.), Paul Churchland (pp. 66-87). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ Press.
Mandik, P. (2008). An epistemological theory of consciousness? In A. Plebe & V. M. D. L. Cruz (Eds.), Philosophy in the Neuroscience Era (pp. 136-158). Rome: Squilibri.
Mandik, P. (forthcoming). Transcending Zombies.
McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. (1998). Lecture III: Intentionality as a relation. Journal Of Philosophy, 95, 471-491.
Pautz, A. (2007). Intentionalism and perceptual presence. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 495.
Peacocke, C. (1998). Nonconceptual Content Defended (Comments on McDowell’s Mind and World). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58, 381–388.
Peacocke, C. (2001). Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content? The Journal of Philosophy, 1, 239–264.
Pelling, C. (2008). Exactness, inexactness, and the non-transitivity of perceptual indiscriminability. Synthese, 164(2), 289-312.
Perez–Carpinell, J., Baldovi, R., de Fez, M. D., & Castro, J. (1998). Color Memory Matching: Time Effect and Other Factors. Color Research and Applications, 23(4), 234– 247.
Prinz, J. (2007). Mental Pointing: Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(9-10), 184-211.
Raffman, D. (1995). On the Persistence of Phenomenology. In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Conscious Experience. Munich: Imprint Academic Verlag.
Raffman, D. (1996). Vagueness and context-relativity. Philosophical Studies, 81(2), 175-192.
Rey, G. (1991). Sensations in a Language of Thought Philosophical Issues, 1(Consciousness), 73-112.
Rey, G. (1993). Sensational sentences. In M. Davies & G. W. Humphreys (Eds.), Consciousness (pp. 240-257). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Rey, G. (2007). Phenomenal Content and the Richness and Determinacy of Colour Experience. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), The Interplay Between Consciousness and Concepts (pp. 112-131). Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and Mind Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Van Gulick, R. (2004). Higher-order global states (HOGS): an alternative higher- order model of consciousness. In R. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: an anthology (pp. 67–92). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.